Sermon for 26 July 2009, 1st Unitarian
Church of Alton, Illinois
PRAGMATISM: A PHILOSOPHY FROM THE U.S.A.
Ronald
J. Glossop
I. Introduction
A. Four months ago I spoke about the
philosophical movement called “existentialism,” an outlook which has achieved some popularity
in this country even though it originated in Europe and has always had much
more influence there.
B.
At that time I noted that existentialists have a wide range of views
with regard to religion ranging from the very pro-Christian “make a
leap-of-faith” don’t-rely-on-reason view of the Danish philosopher Soren
Kierkegaard to the very anti-theistic “God is dead” let’s-take-
evolution-seriously view of German existentialist Friedrich Nietszsche.
C.
I noted that I was discussing the existentialist viewpoint even though I
personally don’t have much sympathy for it and its revolt against the
18th-century Enlightment with its trust in reason and reasonableness
and its optimism about humanity’s capacity for future progress.
D.
In this sermon I want to discuss another outlook in the philosophy of
the last 150 years, one with which I am very sympathetic, namely, pragmatism. It is the only major movement in philosophy
that has originated in this country, and it is one that has had a major
influence on Unitarian Universalist thinking.
E.
Unlike existentialism, pragmatism is much in harmony with the rationalism
and optimism of the Enlightenment, which was also a major
influence in the creation of this country.
II. Pragmatism refers to a very
sophisticated philosophical viewpoint that has many practical implications
within and beyond philosophy.
A.
At its core, pragmatism maintains that ideas or theories are
true to the extent that they work, that is, to the extent that you can
rely on them when you take action.
The Greek word “pragma” means “works which are done” or “things which
are accomplished.” Having true ideas is
like having a good map that reliably helps you to get where you want to go.
B.
The core ideas of pragmatism come from observing how scientists
actually work in order to discover what is true and what is false.
1.
The pragmatists oppose the view of the Rationalists of the 17th
& 18th centuries such as Descartes, Spinoza, and Leibniz who claimed that one
could know what is true on the basis of just rational intuition and the logical
implications of those insights. The geometry
of Euclid was the model of how to acquire knowledge, and it could be
applied to the physical world starting with intuitive insights such as
“Something can’t come from nothing” and “The total amount of matter in the
universe cannot increase or decrease” and
“Nothing can happen without a cause” and “The more perfect cannot come
from the less perfect.” The general
outlook of the Rationalists was that God must exist as the cause of the
physical universe, but Spinoza used the same general Rationalist
approach to claim that reason showed that God must be identical with the
physical universe (pantheism) rather than a separate cause of it.
2.
The pragmatists oppose the view of the Empiricists of the 16th to
the 19th centuries like Francis Bacon and John Stuart Mill on grounds that one
could not acquire knowledge just by using one’s senses unless one had some
prior notion of what is to be looked at or listened to. Just looking at the stars in the heavens or
listening to the sounds in tbe forest is not going to generate knowledge. We need a theory to guide our sensing,
and that prior theory comes from our reason formulating notions about
what might be true.
3.
Pragmatists claimed that in order to acquire knowledge one must
use both reason (to formulate hypotheses or theories about what might be
true, especially about what might cause what) and our senses (to
discover which hypothesis or theory correctly predicts what will happen in a
particular situation).
4.
This way of acquiring knowledge is precisely what scientists do when
they conduct experiments to determine which hypotheses and theories are
true and which are not. Even when there
is a general consensus about what is probably true, we have to conduct experiments
to determine what is in fact true, at least as far as we can determine
that now.
5.
A crucial event in the history of science and very
relevant to pragmatism in the history of philosophy occurred in 1919
during a total eclipse of the sun. The
issue was which of two alternative theories about the nature of the physical
world was true. The physical theory
of Isaac Newton was based on Euclidean geometry and certain “rational”
intuitions such as that light always travels in straight lines and
that if a beam of light was projected from a moving object the actual speed of
the light waves in that beam of light would be the sum of the speed of light
generally and the speed of the moving object.
That is, it seemed evident that the light would go faster if it was
projected from a forward moving object than if it was projected from a
non-moving object or an object moving in the opposite direction. Newton’s theory not only seemed rational but
also relied on verification by many empirical investigations, and it was
accepted by almost everyone. Albert
Einstein’s theory of relativity, on the other hand, was based on different
somewhat counter-intuitive suppositions, namely, that light traveled along
curved paths (but with such a small amount of curvature that it could not
be detected at short distances) and that the speed of light was constant
regardless of the motion of the light source.
It had virtually no support from other physicists. How could we determine which of these two
theories is true? The resolution of the
issue was possible because, as Einstein himself noted, the two theories gave different
predictions about how much variation would take place in the “apparent
position” of the stars during an total eclipse of the sun as opposed to the “observed
position” of the stars at night when the light rays from the stars would not be
bent by the gravitational pull of the sun.
The observations in 1919 turned out to be more in accord with the
predictions based on Einstein’s theory (and this became even more evident
on the basis of further observations).
For most astronomers, these observations proved that Einstein’s
theory of relativity is more correct or true than Newton’s theory. Now the plans for space flights are always
based on the theory of Einstein rather than that of Newton, and they
succeed. The theory that correctly
predicts is the one that is viewed as true, but only as long as
it works. The accepted theory is
always being modified as new evidence is collected.
6.
This need for continuous modification of the accepted view
provides an important corollary for the pragmatist, namely the view of fallibilism,
that is, that what we now regard as true is only tentatively so
and may require modification on the basis of further experiments. The implication is that there are two
different meanings of saying that an idea is true. (1) We usually mean that it is an idea that has
been working up to this point. (2)
But one can also formulate a more absolute idea of truth, namely that,
as American philosopher Charles Sanders Peirce put it, “Truth is what
all people who investigate will ultimately come to believe.” Absolute Truth is an ideal to be
pursued, but is is an ideal that is unattainable as long as more experiences
are possible, that is, as long as time remains. Nevertheless we can be confident that use
of the scientific method allows us to move ever closer to the
ultimate truth. We are approximating
it, even though we never attain it. We
are certainly closer to a correct understanding of the universe than people who
lived a thousand years ago or even two hundred years ago, and we can expect
that continuing scientific experimentation will lead to an even greater
approximation to absolute Truth in the future. That is the optimistic side of
pragmatism.
7.
Fallibilism is a principle of pragmatism that is very relevant
to Unitarian Universalism and to religion generally. It implies that it is very inappropriate
for people to claim that they have the Truth and are very committed to
maintaining that version of the Truth regardless of what new knowledge
may be acquired or what new experiences people may have. Our experience and our knowledge is ever
expanding. Consequently, our commitment,
as that of any scientist, should not be to conclusions that may seem
correct at some particular moment but rather to a method for
discovering new truths, to the method of experimentation and to the continuing
evaluation of beliefs within our community of those who seek the truth and the improvement
of our human society. Our commitment
should be not to any particular past or present conclusions about what
is true or what is good but rather to continuous growth in our
understanding of what is true and what is good.
8.
Pragmatists carry on the Enlightenment focus on the need for humans to
use reason, and for pragmatists reason means the use of
intelligence in solving problems as scientists do when they are developing
hypotheses about what might be the cause of some phenomenon or what
might be done to solve some problem.
It is our capacity to use reason in this sense that makes pragmatists
optimistic about the future even as we need to deal with new problems.
9.
With regard to what pragmatism means in the life of individual
persons, let me refer to my own experiences. I was fortunate to have teachers in my
kindergarten through high school education who were informed by and dedicated
to the ideas of John Dewey. It is no
accident that my commencement address at our high school graduation was titled “Keep
Growing,” the kernel of Dewey’s ideas about education and life—even though
at that time I was not aware of the source of these ideas.
III. Let me mention
some particular well-known American philosophers who are pragmatists.
A.
In connection with the principle of fallibilism, I just mentioned Charles
Sanders Peirce (1839-1914), son of a Harvard professor of mathematics. Peirce had his own chemistry lab at the age
of twelve and was studying philosophy in his teens. He graduated from Harvard and then from the
Lawrence Scientific School of Harvard four years later. He did scientific work for almost two decades
before becoming a professor of philosophy with special interests in mathematical
logic and Boolean algebra, but his interests also included religion and the
nature of language. Fallibilism
and the existence of totally unpredictable chance occurrences were two
of Peirce’s main ideas. Unfortunately,
many of his writings were not published until the early 1930s, twently years
after his death.
B.
One of Peirce’s classmates at Harvard was William James
(1842-1910), younger brother of the famous writer Henry James. William James received much of his education
at various private schools in both the U.S. and Europe. He studied physiology for a while in Germany
and then returned to Harvard for his medical degree in 1869. Three years later he was appointed professor
of psychology at Harvard. His Principles
of Psychology published in 1890 was one of the first scientific textbooks
in the field. Some of his popular
lectures were published as The Will to Believe and Other Essays. In the years 1901-1902 he gave the Gifford
Lectures in Edinburgh, which were published as Varieties of Religious
Experience. A second volume of
James’s essays titled Pragmatism
was published in 1907.
C.
John Dewey (1859-1952) is the most widely known proponent of
pragmatism, though he himself preferred other names for this movement such as
“naturalism,” “instrumentalism,” or “experimentalism.” Dewey was born in Vermont and graduated from
the University of Vermont in 1879. After
teaching in public schools for three years, he went to Johns Hopkins University
to get his Ph.D. in philosophy. He taught
at the University of Michigan for ten years before going to the University of
Chicago where, in addition to teaching philosophy and psychology, he was able
to run a laboratory school focused on educational practices. In 1904 he went to Columbia University in New
York. His lectures in Japan resulted in
the book Reconstruction in Philosophy in 1920. He was also invited to give lectures in
China, Russia, Turkey, and Mexico as well as several European countries. His 40 books include Experience and Nature
(1925) and The Quest for Certainty (1929).
D. Other well-known pragmatists are George
Herbert Mead (1863-1931), Willard van Orman Quine (1908-2000), Donald
Davidson (1917-2003), and Richard Rorty (1931-2007)
IV.
William James and John Dewey
are the philosophers best known as central to the pragmatic movement, but their
views are really quite different, especially with regard to the
role of humans in society and how one finds truth in religion.
A.
William James was a champion of individualism. As a pragmatist, he believed that what
works is true, but he viewed this from a very individualistic point
of view.
1.
For example, if it works for you (that is, makes your life more
satisfactory) to believe that there is a God who guarantees that good will prevail
in the end and that people continue to live after their death, then these
beliefs are true for you (even if they might not be true for some other
individuals).
2. Furthermore, James thought that you could and
should consciously adopt views that make life more satisfactory. Early in his own life, James experienced a
period of depression as a result of reading material showing that people do not
have free will but are merely the products of their heredity and
environment. After reading an essay with
an opposing viewpoint by French philosopher Renouvier, he wrote in his diary “My
first act of free will shall be to believe in free will.” He recovered his health, and from then on he
championed what he called “the will to believe.” Deliberately adopt views that make your life
happier.
B.
John Dewey, on the other hand, always saw individuals as part
of a community. One of his books, Individualism Old and New (1929), tells
how his own progressive view of individualism differs from the “rugged
individualism” often associated with this country.
1.
What matters is not so much what works for you as a separate
individual but what works for the whole community. Scientists work as part of a scientific
community engaged in a collective search for truth which serves the
whole human community.
2.
This concern with the whole human community led Dewey to be especially
concerned about the education of children and about promoting
democracy as a way of community decision-making. He insisted that philosophers should
not be engaged in abstract discussions of little interest to the rest of the
society but should be leaders in addressing the problems of the whole human
society and how to advance the welfare of the individuals in that society.
3.
Dewey’s main work concerning religion is titled A Common Faith. In it he argues that humanity needs the
notion of “God” or “the divine” as the concept of ideal possibilities to
be realized which can arouse emotion and thus promote the growth
of the ideal and its realization. He
denigrates militant atheism for lacking natural piety, for viewing the natural
world as indifferent and even hostile rather than as supportive of humanity and
our ideals.
4.
I think that the seven purposes & principles regularly listed on the
back of our Sunday bulletin provide a good summary of the ideal possibilities
to which Dewey alludes. This church is a
community committed to these ideals and part of the larger human community.
V. Henry Nelson Wieman (1884-1975) is a recent
Unitarian Universalist theologian whose later ideas are unquestionably based on
the pragmatic views of John Dewey.
A.
Wieman’s father was a Presbyterian minister, and Henry himself became a
Presbyterian minister in St. Joseph, Missouri in 1911. But in 1915 he resigned and enrolled at
Harvard University where he earned his Ph.D. in philosophy in 1917. After teaching philosophy at Occidental
College in Los Angeles for 10 years, he was invited to become Professor of
Christian Theology at the University of Chicago. He resigned from Chicago in 1947 and then
taught at the University of Oregon and the University of West Virginia. He joined the Unitarian Church in Eugene, Oregon
in 1949, and in 1950 was granted ministerial fellowship with the American
Unitarian Association.
B.
In 1951 he took a position teaching philosophy at the University of
Houston. He became embroiled in a racial
controversy between two Unitarian churches and ended up antagonizing both of
them. But just then he then received a
letter from Martin Luther King, Jr. indicating his intention to do his
dissertation on “A Comparison of the Idea of God in the Thinking of Paul Tillich
and Henry Nelson Wieman.”
C.
In 1956 Wieman was invited to join the faculty of philosophy at Southern
Illinois University at Carbondale, where he taught for ten years while also
being active in the Carbondale Unitarian Fellowship. John Broyer, who gave our organ to
this church, went to SIUC in order to study under Wieman. Our church library contains a book about
Wieman co-edited by Broyer and William Minor titled Creative Interchange: A
Festschrift in honor of Henry Nelson Wieman (1982) as well as two of Wieman’s
books, The Source of Human Good (1946) and Man’s Ultimate Commitment
(1958). These two books provide insight
into Wieman’s view that we need to change our concept of God from a supernatural
transcendent personal being to a naturalistic force operating within the
world which is responsible for making human life better. We can discover by critical empirical
investigation that this “source of human good” (which we can readily call
“God”) is in fact the process of creative interchange we observe at work in
democratic communities. For Wieman
it is this process of creative interchange that we should make central to our
religious communities and to which we should make our ultimate commitment.
D.
In 1970, just six days after his death, Wieman was awarded the Unitarian
Universalist Association Award for Distinguished Service to the Cause of
Liberal Religion.
V. What can we say in conclusion?
A. Pragmatism means being ready to
experiment with new ways and focusing on getting problems solved,
qualities which are associated with this country all over the world.
B. Pragmatism
is but one philosophical movement, but its origins are in this country, and it champions
many of the ideas about using intelligence and scientific
experimentation to solve problems which are found in our national culture and
in our Unitarian Universalist religion.
C. These pragmatic ideas of experimentalism
and fallibilism and not being dogmatic and being ready to
adopt new ideas and working together in a democratic community
for the welfare of the whole world are evident in the basic purposes and
principles of our Unitarian Universalist religion.
D.
It seems to me that there is a definite harmony between the
philosophical outlook of pragmatism and the commitments of our Unitarian Universalist Association.
Return to First Unitarian Church of Alton - Selected Sermons Page