THE BASIC BASICS OF MORALITY
I. Introduction: The beginning of a new year, as
well as of a new century and of a new millenium, would seem to be a good
time to make and/or renew resolutions about how to be a better person and
to rethink what is involved in being a good person. It is this latter
issue that I would like to address this morning. What is basic in
morality, and what is the
foundation for this basic principle? That is why my title is
"The Basic Basics of Morality."
II. If there is any basic principle of morality, it seems to be
the Golden Rule: "Do unto others as you would have them do unto you."
Or to cite the Confucian negative form: "Do not do to others what you would
not have done to you." This basic principle of morality has a prominent
place in all of the world's major religions and has been enunciated by
pagan philosophers both before and after Jesus. There is no evidence
of any historical diffusion of this widely accepted principle, so it seems
to be a fundamental ethical belief.
A. If we are searching
for the basic foundation of morality, we need to ask whether adopting the
Golden Rule as a moral guide is dependent on believing in God.
1. The first argument against dependence on belief in God is that
the Golden Rule is cited, as just mentioned, even by persons and societies
where there is no belief in God in the traditional sense. Thus belief
in God does not seem to be a necessary foundation.
2. One argument for the view that belief in God is a necessary foundation
for the Golden Rule is the argument that God must be assumed to exist as
the basis for believ-ing that the universe is a moral universe.where it
makes sense to follow moral rules If there is no God, then the universe
just is and it has no higher purpose which can provide a
basis for morality. It is also sometimes claimed that the Golden
Rule is a basic princi-ple of morality simply because it is what God has
commanded, and what God has commanded is what determines what our duties
are.
a. But it does not seem that the universe must be morally based for
me to be moral. Why can't I just decide to be moral even if the universe
is amoral or even immoral. Why can't I just want to do what is right
whether the universe "cares" one whit one way or the other?
b. Also is it appropriate to bring up the issue of what God commands?
I think not. Even if there is a God who commands something, am I
not able to discern whether what is being commanded is good or not?
It is not appropriate to argue that God is good and therefore that whatever
God commands is good. How does one know that God is good if the commandment
given by God is not good? The goodness or badness of the commandment
is more evident than the goodness or badness of God, so let us focus on
the goodness or badness of commandment itself rather than worrying about
its source.
3. A second argument for the view that the Golden Rule requires a
divine being is that there will be no motivation or incentive to obey the
Golden Rule without a divine being to enforce it by rewarding those who
obey it and punishing those who disobey it.
a. But if one obeys a rule only in order to gain some reward, one
is not acting morally no matter what the rule is. On the other hand,
if the moral thing to do is to follow the rule, then one should follow
the rule whether or not there is an extrinsic reward.
b. This is a point that needs to be emphasized because it is so often
argued that morality requires that there be punishments for disobeying
moral rules and rewards for obeying them. In fact, to argue in that
manner undermines the very notion of morality, of doing what is right just
because it is right and not because of some extrinsic reward or punishment,
either in this life or the next. That approach would convert everything
that seems to be morality into mere enlightened self-interest: I'll
be good so I go to heaven.
B. It is not only
in popular morality that this Golden Rule principle is basic. Many
philosophers of morality have also argued for this same principle.
One of the best known of these efforts is "The Categorical Imperative"
enunciated by the famous 18th-century German philosopher Immanuel Kant.
As befits a philosopher, he stated the principle in a more sophisticated
way. The English-language form of that basic principle of morality
is: "Always act in such a manner that you
could will that the maxim of your action should become a universal
law." Modern philosophers refer to this as the universalizability principle.
The moral law is such that it cannot vary from person to person.
The height of immorality is when one does something and then maintains
that it would be wrong for others in the same situation to do likewise.
Kant returns again and again to the idea that a law (including a moral
law) must be a law for everyone--including oneself. No one, no matter
how rich or talented or powerful, can be above the law.
C. You will note that
I did not say that all philosophers have argued for this Golden Rule principle.
To get to the basic basics of morality we must consider one who did
not think so highly of this principle, namely, another German philosopher--this
one from the 19th century--Friedrich Nietzsche.
1. Although Nietzsche is a philosopher, by profession he was a philologist,
a student of the development of language. His study of moral language
led him to the conclusion that there are in fact two very different kinds
of morality in human society.
a. One kind of morality is that developed by the upper classes, by
the elite. Nietzsche calls it "master morality" or "aristocratic morality,"
the viewpoint of those who have talent and wealth and power. This
type of
morality is focused on excellence, on what makes one a superior person.
It is this kind of morality which attracted Nietzsche. For him it
represented the thinking of those who "have what it takes" to confront
life, to rise above mediocrity to excellence. Master morality reflects
an optimistic individualism and disdains the pessimistic collectivist viewpoint
of the
common man. Master morality is opposed to democracy and socialism
and any other kind of egalitarianism.
b. The second kind of morality for Nietzsche is what he calls "slave
morality." It represents the moral viewpoint of the masses, of the
have-nots This type of morality is focused on the evil done by those
upper class individuals who regard themselves as above the law. It is formulated
out of resentment against those whose superior position allows them to
be unjust & to ignore the concerns of the poor & weak. That
is why slave morality is usually expressed in negative commandments about
what is not allowed--adultery, killing, stealing, arrogance. For
slave
morality, it is precisely the Golden Rule which aims to put some restraints
on what the powerful can do. They may think that their talent and
upper class social position entitle them to do anything they want in order
to reach a higher level of excellence, but the rules of justice (that is,
equality) forbid that.
2. Because Nietzsche was a champion of aristocratic morality as against
slave morality and thus was not supportive of the Golden Rule, some other
philosophers have called Nietzsche an immoralist. But name-calling will
not solve the problem of what is moral and what is immoral. If we
are going to support the Golden Rule as a basic prin-ciple
of morality, we must address Nietzsche's contempt for egalitarian slave
morality.
3. Nevertheless, this discussion of Nietzsche's view has brought
to attention what previously may have escaped our notice, namely, that
the Golden Rule emphasizes equality in contrast to the alternative aristocratic
view which may be capsulized as the "rank-has-its-privileges" view.
III. Although the Golden Rule was widely known in ancient civilizations,
it seems at first to have been applied only within one's own society.
It would have been an important principle in maintaining peace within the
society. As far as I know, the first philosophers to extend it to
all humans were the Stoic philosophers in the third century BC. It
became very
popular among the Romans, including the soldiers of the Roman legions,
leading intellectuals such as Cicero and Seneca, the slave-turned-teacher
Epictetus, and the much-admired Emperor Marcus Aurelius.
A. The Stoics based
their acceptance of the Golden Rule on the belief that every human (or
at least every man) carried within himself a part of the divine, a rational
capability of seeing things from a general or disinterested point
of view. This meant that there was a basic equality among men regardless
of their social rank. The logical consequence of this view, as the
Stoics themselves realized, is that slavery (the idea that one person could
be the possession of another
person) is immoral. I suppose that a few persons even applied
this principle to women, but the accepted view in society still was that
women were the possessions of their husbands. The Stoic view that
slavery was morally wrong also was not generally accepted until much later.
B. According to the
Stoics each man was able to comprehend the divine order in the world and
to realize that everything happened in accord with the laws of nature,
which could also be understood as the will of God. The Stoics extended
this notion of law and order to the realm of morality arguing that every
man could realize that there are rules of good behavior that constitute
a natural or moral law which everyone could know intuitively. When
put into its most concise form, this moral law was the Golden Rule.
C. Kant's notion of
the categorical imperative was basically a new more philosophic-ally sophisticated
way of saying what the Stoics and other philosophers such as Thomas Aquinas
and John Locke had said in defense of a
natural moral law. It is a view that has come to most Americans
through the words of the Declaration of Independence which note that men
have certain unalienable rights such as life, liberty, and the pursuit
of happiness. What does not so often come to consciousness is that
if all men have these natural rights, then all men also have natural obligations
to
respect these natural rights of others. That is, the moral
law works both ways, giving us obligations as well as rights.
D. Thomas Jefferson
got the idea of unalienable rights from John Locke, and so did many other
Enlightenment thinkers. In fact, the notion of natural rights and
the conse-quent need for a democratic political system were among the most
important ideas of the Enlightenment. Recall the slogan of the French
Revolution: Liberté, Egalité, Fraternité.
E. It is worth noting, however, that natural rights for women
still did not fare very well despite Condorcet's 1787 treatise defending
them. Four years later woman author Marie Olympe de Gouges published
a declaration on the rights of women, but she was be-headed two years later
for opposing Robespierre. At the turn of the century 100 years ago,
New Zealand was the only country in the world where women were allowed
to vote.
F. The main point
I want to make here is the intimate connection between the widely accepted
basic principle of the Golden Rule on the one hand and the ideals of equality
and democracy on the other. These are diametrically opposed to Nietzsche's
"rank-has-its-privileges" view and the ideals of elitism & aristocratic
morality on the other. Though the
individualistic Nietzsche was by no means a fascist, still his elitist
ideology provided support for some aspects of later Nazi racism and antipathy
to democracy and the notion of a natural universal moral law.
IV. It is worth mentioning that our country's democratic, capitalistic
ideology contains a tension between the opposing principles of egalitarianism
and individualistic elitism.
A. As already noted,
democracy is the application of universalistic egalitarianism in the arena
of politics. This focus on equality under the law and on not allowing
a few rich and powerful persons to run the show is the leftist part of
our national ideology. This egalitarian viewpoint tends to be emphasized
in our political system by the Democratic Party, the party of the down-and-outers.
B. But what also needs
to be noted is that our capitalistic economic system is the application
of Nietzsche's individualistic get-the-group-controlled-government-out-of-my-way
ideal in the arena of economics. This focus on the desirability of
competition and on letting the winner enjoy the reward of winning is the
rightist part of our national
ideology. This individualistic elitist viewpoint tends to be
emphasized in our political system by the Republicans, the party of those
who are succeeding in the competition.
C. My own view is
that the tension between these two opposing ideologies is desir-able and
that a balance between them should be maintained. The problem which
I see developing at the present time within our country is that the leftist
democratic political system is losing its battle to keep some control on
the rich-get-richer rightist capitalistic economic system as our politicians,
our elections, and our news sources are being taken over by the rich to
further enrich themselves. The problem is duplicated at the global
level where the lack of a democratic world federation allows the rich to
advance their interests without the kind of political check that has often
been exercised on them within democratic
nation-states.
V. The balance or tension between the leftist democratic political
system and the rightist capitalistic economic system is desirable, but
I think we must put more emphasis on the preservation of the egalitarian
leftist viewpoint.
A. This added push
is required partly because of the current trends away from a democratic
check both within our country and within the world. As we all know,
the gap between rich and poor is widening both within our country and within
our world.
B. Aside from the
current trend, there is also a natural tendency for this increasing concentration
of wealth and power to occur, so we must constantly struggle against it.
Those who have wealth and power use that wealth and power to get more both
in the economic arena and in the political arena. Furthermore, the
wealth and power tends to get passed on to their limited group of descendants.
If it were just a matter of how much could be amassed in one generation,
the problem would be much more manageable.
C. Though the incentive
of individual rewards must be maintained in order that pro-gress will continue,
it is even more important to maintain the moral constraint that comes with
application of the Golden Rule.
VI. The basic insight which underlies the Golden Rule and the
leftist, egalitarian way of thinking connected with it is the recognition
of the great role which luck or fortune plays in all of our lives.
A. The important role
of luck becomes evident to everyone in accidents or natural disasters or
fortuitous misfortunes. As a result, there is usually much public
sympathy for the victims of such obvious bad luck.
B. What is not so
evident without special effort of thought is the extremely important role
of luck in making each of us what we are.
1. No one chooses when or where to be born. Yet these are very
crucial factors in making us what we are.
2. No one chooses their biological make-up, which includes such crucial
matters as what race one is, what sex one is, how intelligent one is, whether
one has special talents or special disabilities, whether one has genes
for good health or a debilitating disease or sickness.
3. No one chooses what their parents and early environment will be
like. Will one live one's early years in love and prosperity or in
suffering and poverty? That again is totally outside of our control.
C. Given all these
factors which are outside of our control, all who have a relatively happy
and successful life can only be very thankful for what has come their way.
D. Any personal pride--in
what one has accomplished, in what one has, in what kind of life one has
lived--is totally inappropriate. Of course, it will be satisfying
to believe that we are doing the best we can given what opportunities and
abilities we have, but in the end we need to realize that even that drive
to do well is a gift or dependent on a gift that ultimately is not within
our own control.
E. All these thoughts
are what make me call Nietzsche and other advocates of the rightist or
elitist viewpoint "immoralists." They are guilty of hubris, of thinking
that their great accomplishments of whatever kind are their own doing rather
than the result of a huge number of factors over which they had and have
no control.
F. I ally myself with
the friends of the Golden Rule and egalitarianism. I agree with Albert
Schweitzer that one of the most basic of all principles of morality, one
which goes even beyond the Golden Rule, is "Good fortune obligates."
Anyone who thinks otherwise just has not appreciated the overwhelming role
of luck in human life.
G. Appreciating the
fundamental role of luck in our lives is one of the basic basics of morality.
As I have noted, acceptance of the Golden Rule is totally unrelated to
believing in God or to expecting some kind of personal reward either now
or in some after-life for doing what is the right thing to do. On
the contrary, let us always keep before us the thought of how much our
lives and the lives of others have been and still are dependent on forces
over which we and they have no control and remember that that is the basic
foundation for the Golden Rule, one of the most basic of all moral principles.
© 2000 Dr. Ronald J. Glossop
|