WHAT IS EXISTENTIALISM AND WHY DOES IT MATTER?
WHAT
IS EXISTENTIALISM AND WHY DOES IT MATTER?
Ronald
J. Glossop
I. Introduction
A. Not long ago Khleber Van Zandt
mentioned in a sermon that the well-known theologian Paul Tillich was an
existentialist. After the service
several people asked me, “What exactly is an existentialist?”
B.
That experience led me to decide that I would address that issue in my
next sermon.
C.
I feel that I should alert you to the fact that this explanation comes
from someone who does not have much sympathy for existentialism. Nevertheless, as a professor of philosophy I
have spent much of my time explaining various philosophical views with which I
am not particulary sympathetic.
D.
I will do my best to help you understand what Existentialism is,
but then I will conclude by giving my critique of it.
II. Existentialism refers to a viewpoint
expressed by several different 19th- and 20th-century philosophers whose views differ very
much from each other with regard to religion, ethics and other particular
issues.
A.
Among the better known philosophers & theologians usually designated
“existentialists” are Soren Kierkegaard, Friedrich Nietzsche,
Jean Paul Sartre, Simone de Beauvoir, Albert Camus, Martin
Heidegger, Karl Jaspers, Karl Barth, Paul Tillich,
and Martin Buber. Though Tillich
later came to the United States, all of these thinkers were Europeans. Even the American philosopher William
James, who with some justification could be said to exhibit some
“existentialist” tendencies, was much influenced by his education in Europe.
B.
Here is my short definition of “existentialism:” existentialism is the view that there are no
general rules to guide human beings concerning how they should act, and
especially that no ethical rules can be derived from consideration of
some supposedly determinate human nature which applies to all humans,
because individual human beings are completely free to determine
their own nature by the choices they make.
C.
To understand how there can be such a wide range of views espoused by
thinkers all of whom are called “existentialists,” it may be helpful to see existentialists
as philosophers and theologians in revolt against reason and reasonableness
and universal principles and the notion that all people are or
even should be the same or should follow the same principles. Existentialists have many different views
because there are many different ways of rebelling against reason.
D.
The traditional view adopted by philosophers up through the 18th-century
Enlightenment is another view called “essentialism,” a view which goes
back to the classical philosophers Plato and Aristotle. According to this “essentialism,”
there are ideal Forms or Essences to which individuals aim to
conform themselves, whether one is considering living things like oak trees
or inanimate things like circles and other geometric figures. Why does an acorn grow to be an oak
tree? Because it is trying to embody
the perfect Form of Oak Tree. When
trying to draw a circle, one naturally tries to draw the most perfect circle
one can. The definition of a
circle in geometry is the definition of what a perfect circle should
be. The ideal definition of
anything is the one that correctly captures the essence of that kind of
thing. The essence also describes the perfect
one, the ideal archetype of this kind of thing.
E. In the same way, the definition
of “human being” will indicate what a perfect human being should
be, what the essence of being human is. A human being is a rational animal. Reason is what makes humans different
from other animals. The essence
of being human is being rational.
That is true of all humans.
Plato and Aristotle and later philosophers develop their different views
of what being rational involves, but all agree that there is a common essence
for all human beings and that the ideal human being is the one who is completely
rational.
F.
This essentialism is what existentialists are protesting
against. One way of succinctly stating
their view is to say that in the case of human beings “Existence precedes
essence.” People determine what
character they will have by the choices they make. There is no pre-existing essence to which
they are obliged to conform.
G.
In other words, existentialists deny that there is some “Essence
of Human Being,” some ideal of being completely rational, which all
humans should seek to embody. Humans can
choose to be whatever they want to be, including not being rational.
H.
Here is the way that Russian novelist Dostoevsky puts it in Notes
from Underground: “You see,
gentlemen, reason is an excellent thing; there’s no disputing that. But reason is nothing but reason and satisfies
only the rational side of one’s nature, while will is a
manifestation of the whole life, that is, of the whole human life, including
reason and all the impulses. And
although our life, at least in this manifestation of it, is often worthless,
yet it is life and not simply extracting square roots.”
I.
Existentialists emphasize exerting one’s will rather than using
one’s reason to reach conclusions about what is true or what is good,
that is, how one should live one’s life.
J. Let me briefly review the basic ideas of a few
existentialist theologians & philosophers.
1. Kierkegaard, a Christian existentialist, argues that there
are no good arguments to prove that Jesus was resurrected or that
Jesus is God, but he believes that one does not need to depend on
rational arguments. What is required
of believers is not the finding of rational arguments or good evidence
but making a “leap of faith” as an act of will. Religion is based on faith, not on relying on
reason to figure out what is true or good.
2.
Nietzsche, an atheistic
existentialist, argues that it is disgraceful for those who have great talent
to adopt a universalistic moral point of view based on empathy with
those who are less fortunate, what he calls the “slave morality”
advanced by Jews and Christians and socialists and have-nots generally. Those who are superior should recognize
their superiority over the masses.
They should adopt a “master morality” which moves them to achieve
even greater excellence, to become supermen not restrained by the universalistic
egalitarian herd morality of the ordinary masses.
3.
William James, another
Christian philosopher, argues in “The Will to Believe” that on issues such as
whether there is life after death, issues where the objective
evidence is not conclusive, one should use one’s will to adopt
beliefs which produce contentment.
Belief should be guided by will rather than a quest for good
reasons which can never be satisfied.
III. Another theme in much existentialist thought
is that reality itself is not rational.
There is no rhyme or reason for what exists. Reality at bottom is “absurd,” “a tale
told by an idiot.”
A.
Contrary to the earlier view that “God’s in his heaven and all is right
with the world,” the existentialists believe that “God is dead,” at
least in the sense of a being who has created a rational, orderly world with a
moral order which all humans must follow or be punished in eternity.
B.
If there is any purpose in life or any kind of moral order, it will have
to be a purpose or a moral order created by humans, not one that is
found ready-made in a God-created universe.
C.
Individuals must create their own purpose or meaning in life as
well as their own moral standards. Furthermore, this purpose and these
standards will not be the same for everyone. Existentialists advocate a radical
individualism. There is no truth or
morality which is valid for everyone.
IV. Existentialists focus on will
and choice and the notion that one can choose to not be
rational.
A.
But, why not be rational?
Whether the matter to be decided is what to believe or what to
to do, why not believe or act on the basis of good reasons?
B.
What is the alternative to believing or acting on the basis of
good reasons? It is to believe or
act on the basis of impulses or causes which are not good
reasons. One believes or acts on the
basis of contingent factors. What
belief did you happen to hear first or most often? What do
you happen to feel like doing at a particular moment or what
is everyone else doing? Such
haphazard beliefs are exactly those beliefs which cannot stand
up to challenges of evidence or good arguments against them. Such haphazard actions are exactly the
actions that one regrets later, saying to oneself, “Why did I do
that?” In this context that means asking
for a cause, not a reason.
If you had had a good reason for not doing it, you would not
have done it. It must be some kind
of nonrational cause that explains why you did it. For example, would Kierkegaard have been a
Christian if he had lived in Asia?
C.
Existentialists seem to view a free choice as a choice not
constrained by reason. But in fact,
such nonrational choices, whether related to belief or to action,
are exactly the beliefs and actions which we cannot rationally
defend. They are the result of nonrational
impulses and nonrational causes.
Those are precisely the unjustified beliefs that are readily
overturned and the irrational actions which we later regret
and find to be indefensible.
D.
Undoubtedly we are not always rational. Sometimes we believe things which we have no
good reason to believe. Sometimes we do
things that we cannot rationally defend.
We all are imperfect beings.
But there is something paradoxical about the existentialist desire of not
wanting to be constrained by reason, not wanting to be guided by what is
rational. That would result in being
guided by haphazard causes and irrational impulses and addictions.
E.
It is true that we humans are not disembodied minds, which some
philosophers of the past viewed as the ideal.
We undoubtedly are animals, but we can use reason to guide our beliefs
and behavior rather than just adopting any ideas we happen to hear or following
the impulses of the moment.
F.
We do not need to search for true ideas and good ideals completely
on our own. We can rely on the
discoveries and reasoning of scientists and others to help us learn what is true. We can attend to the insights of others and
the laws of our governments in order to help us to decide what is good. We are part of an evolving human society
which is continually gaining in knowledge about what is true and improving our
understanding of what is good. There is collective
knowledge about what is true and collective understanding about what
is good.
G.
With regard to the view that humans must create our own purposes
in life and our own morality, our own ideas about what is good, it seems to me
that we only need to recognize that that has always been our human condition. We may have had myths about what has
been done and planned by the gods or God and about what moral principles have
been handed down by the gods or God, but these beliefs and practices
have always been human creations.
What is to prevent us from doing the same things without the imaginative
myths about supernatural sources of the information and the moral ideals? These myths from the past in fact have
become obstacles to gaining more reliable truths about the nature of
reality and to having a better understanding of how to create a better human
society.
V. I believe that Aristotle and the essentialists
have it right.
A.
That is, all of us do have a concept of the ideal human being,
and the understanding that that mature, fully developed human being is one who
is guided by reason. The ideal person is someone who tries to believe
what is objectively true and tries to act in accord with what is generally
recognized as good for humanity as a whole in the long run.
B.
We all in fact fall short of being that ideal person we would like to
be, but that is not something that makes us glad. Who doesn’t want to be an ideal person?
C.
There are many ways of being irrational, of being impulsive and
uncaring, of being childish and selfish, but are any of them desirable?
D.
Existentialists may think that being free means not being
constrained by reason, but essentialists believe just the opposite,
namely, that being guided by reason is the epitome of freedom
& the necessary means for realizing the ideal of being good persons
and developing a good human community.
Return to First Unitarian Church of Alton - Selected Sermons Page