Sermon for 4 December 2005, 1st
Unitarian Church of Alton, Illinois
THE EVOLVING
IDEA OF GOD
Ronald J. Glossop
I. Introduction
A.
Let me begin by noting that my use of the singular word "God" does
not mean that I want to exclude the idea of many "gods" from the
discussion.
B.
In fact, that is exactly where I want to begin our discussion of this
issue. It seems that the earliest
notion of "gods" assumed that there are other beings something
like ourselves who cause things to occur just as we are able to do. If a rock comes unexpectedly tumbling down a
mountain and hits me, isn't that very much like someone throwing a rock at me
in order to injure me? And on other
occasions something very unexpected can help me, like a wave in the river
throwing me up on shore as I was struggling to keep from drowning. Didn't "someone" give me some
help? Since primitive people had virtually
no understanding of why things happen, it was easy to suppose that there must
be other conscious beings somewhat like ourselves causing these events to
happen.
C.
At first, it would be unusual events that were
particularly hurtful or helpful that would be viewed as the
results of the activities of "the gods," but eventually
everyday happenings which were not understood would also be viewed that way. Why does the sun come up each morning and go
down each evening? Why does the regular
changing of the seasons take place? Why
do seeds grow? Why do some women become
pregnant while others do not? When lightning lights up the sky and loud thunder
shakes the earth, doesn't that show that "someone" up there is
angry? Any child can see that! When it doesn't rain for long periods so that
the crops don't grow, doesn't that show that "someone" is unhappy
with us? And when the weather is good
and the harvest is abundant, doesn't that show that "someone" is
bestowing blessings on us? What is more
natural than to feel grateful to that "someone"?
D.
What we treat today as impersonal "forces of nature" and
purely fortuitous events were viewed by these primitive people as
intentional acts of the "gods."
Since our ancestors would not be able to see the bodies of the gods
doing these things, it was not difficult to think that the gods were
nonmaterial "spirits" or that they were too far away to be
seen.
E.
It doesn't take much imagination on our part to understand how these
primitive people would think. Many
people today still think the same way.
If there is much destruction from a hurricane or an earthquake, that
must be some kind of punishment from some god or gods. If some individual is in such a disaster but
manges to escapes injury, then that person must have been saved by some god or
gods. Or if our military forces are
experiencing victories and conquering territory from the enemy, it must be
because god or the gods are on our side.
II. What do these observations tell us about
how people, both primitive people and people alive today all over the
world, think about the gods or god?
A.
One could note first how uncredibly egoistical the whole scenario
is. The gods who control nature are like us. They think like us, and their
intentions can produce changes in the world just as ours can. And the gods are very concerned about us,
doing things to hurt us or help us both individually and collectively. In fact, they are like our parents and
our rulers trying to get us to behave as they want us to behave. They can perform miracles to reward us when
we obey, and they can cause catastrophes to punish us when we disobey.
B. But this observation about human
egotism is a side point. With
regard to my main thesis about the evolving idea of god, the point is to
note is that these gods have power.
They can work through nature on a rather regular or natural basis
(in which case they are what we would call personifications of natural
forces). Or they can work on a very irregular
or supernatural basis (as when they bring about "miracles" and
"inexplicable catastrophes").
But in either case the gods are viewed as beings that can make things
happen. The gods have power. And any supposed beings or gods that can't
make things happen, that don't have power, can't really be gods.
C.
So why worship or sacrifice to such gods? Because they have power to help you
or hurt you. They can give you what you
want if you please them, and they can punish you if you displease them. The relationship is the same as to parents
and to the earthly rulers. The chief
virtue for the individual is unquestioning obedience, and the motivation for
worship or sacrifice is escape punishment and to have more for yourself and
those you like.
D.
Also note what is not important.
It doesn't matter whether these gods themselves are morally good
or morally bad. Think of the
gods and goddesses of the Greeks and Romans.
There is no appeal to worship them because of their moral
goodness. What is relevant is their
power to help the individual get whatever that person wants. For example, in this system of religion, if
I want some person of the opposite sex to fall in love with me, then I must do
all that I can to get Aphrodite or Venus or whatever the goddess of love is
called to help me. I need to give
sacrifices to that goddess and pray to her and do whatever the priestesses at
her temple ask of me. If that sounds
very much like the religious views of some contemporaries with regard to the
gods, don't be surprised. Of course, now
you might need to include not only what you get or don't get in this life
but also the even better or even worse things you might get in the
after-life if you please or don't please some gods and their priests and
religious institutions. And don't limit
your thoughts to Christianity. This is
the nature of much popular religion in all times and places. The gods get worshipped because they have
power to help you get what you want.
It really isn't much different from children wanting to please Santa
Claus to get the Christmas presents they want.
III. One characteristic ascribed to the gods
already mentioned, and one which was especially emphasized in ancient India, is
that the gods are mental or spiritual beings (as in one respect we humans
also are).
A.
The emphasis on the mental or spiritual aspect of the gods has
often been accompanied by a denigrating of the value of the whole physical
world, including our own bodies.
B.
The resulting "idealistic" or "mentalistic" outlook
claims that the physical world is only a product of the mind, that is, that the
physical world is a dream-like or illusory thing which depends for its
existence on mind or spirit and consequently that mental reality
(ideas and thoughts) is a more basic
kind of reality than the physical reality known through our senses.
C. This emphasis on the mental has been applied not only to the
relation between the gods and nature but also to the relation between mind or
spirit and the physical body within the individual human. Instead of the modern scientific view
that our bodies have physical brains which produce the mental world, the
Hindu philosophers advanced the view that each person is really an
immaterial somewhat god-like enduring mind or SOUL that gets
"incorporated" into a series of physical bodies. This idea of the reality of an enduring mind
or soul has also been advanced by others who have rejected the reincarnation
doctrine of the Hindus.
D.
Since the mental or spiritual is more real and enduring than the
physical both with regard to the relation between gods and nature and with
regard to the relation between the individual soul and its body, it was
concluded not only by the Hindus but also by many others that the mental or
spiritual aspect of reality is good while the physical aspect of reality
is bad. Consequently, the goal of
individual humans should be to escape from the down-grading influence of their
physical bodies in order to become purely spiritual. The Hindus developed the
view that when individual souls no longer desire to have a body, then they will
be able to escape from the cycle of continual rebirths and will no longer be
differentiated from god or the ultimate mind or spirit. They will have reached nirvana.
IV. Another feature that came to be associated
with divinity is concern for moral goodness. Why worship gods if they are not concerned about promoting what
is good? The shift from an interest in
the power of the gods to provide assistance to us individually or
collectively to a concern about moral goodness was at least tangentially
related to the shift from polytheism to monotheism.
A. As nearly as we can discover, the idea
of monotheism was first put forth in ancient Egypt by Akhenaten
in the 14th century BCE. He apparently
believed that the sun is God. If
you are going to worship some object in the natural world, the sun is not a bad
choice. Think of how dependent on the
sun all aspects of life on Earth are.
It seems possible that this focus on the sun as god represented not only
a turn from polytheism to monotheism but also a shift from supernaturalism to a
kind of naturalism. But the
revolutionary reforms of Akhenaton lasted only 30 years before a new dynasty in
Egypt reestablished the old polytheistic religion.
B.
We tend to associate monotheism with Judaism, and there is little
doubt that the Jews did eventually make a great point of their belief that
there is only one God, Yahweh. But also
there is little doubt that the Jews were not originally
monotheists. They, like others at that
time, believed that there were many gods.
Yahweh was just the god who protected them.
C.
There was a general assumption that when groups won wars against other
groups, it was because the god of the winning side was more powerful than the
gods of the defeated groups. What
counted was whose god was more powerful.
D.
Rather typically, Jews expected that Yahweh would help them in their
struggles against other peoples. But
they also had some rather unusual ideas, namely that Yahweh expected
their exclusive devotion (no worshipping of or sacrificing to other
gods) and also moral behavior within the group (no killing, no adultery,
no stealing, no bearing of false witness, no coveting of what others had). Here we see a connection starting to develop
between being religious on the one hand and acting morally on the
other, a connection which would have seemed somewhat ridiculous to most
worshippers of gods in polytheistic systems.
E.
Then came a most revolutionary development in the history of
religion. In 722 BCE the enemy
Assyrians conquered the southern part of the territory controlled by the Jews,
and in 586 BCE the enemy Babylonians conquered the northern part. The victors carried off many of the Jews
into captivity in Babylon. But instead
of concluding that the gods of the Assyrians and Babylonians were more powerful
than their own god Yahweh as one might have expected, the Jewish prophets
told them that Yahweh has deliberately allowed them to be defeated because
they had not carried out their side of their convenant with Yahweh. They had begun to sacrifice to other gods
and had failed to live morally within their community. They departed from the idea that the power
of the gods in their struggles with one another was the only thing that
mattered. They adopted the new view
that the important thing was "righteousness," that is, doing
the right thing. In fact, some of their
prophets even said that being morally good was more pleasing to Yahweh than
offering sacrifices at the temple.
V. The next step in the evolution of the idea
of god was that god was concerned with moral behavior not only within the
Jewish or national community but also with moral conduct toward all
other humans.
A.
This shift to a universal moral concern on the part of God is
usually associated with the development of Christianity where the
religious community came to include all believers, not just Jews,
regardless of their ethnicity or the national community from which they came or
how rich or poor they were. In fact, moral
conduct was required even with respect to non-believers, to those outside the
community.
B.
This shift to a universal moral concern can also be seen in Greek
philosophy where Socrates declares that he is a citizen not just of
Athens or Greece but of the whole world as well as in Stoic philosophy
where it was maintained that there is a trace of divinity within every human
being, a doctrine which led the Stoics to be the first to condemn slavery.
C.
It seems that the universalistic moral concern in Christianity may have
been influenced by Paul's familiarity with Stoic philosophy since the
book of Acts (17:28) reports that Paul quoted a Stoic poet ("in God we
live and move and have our being") in his preaching.
D.
But the idea of God's power was continued, for the theistic
Christians in the possibility of miracles to help believers and for the
pantheistic Stoics in the order found in nature.
VI. The idea that God is both powerful
and concerned about goodness ran into the difficult Problem of Evil
when both of these characteristics were pushed to the extreme. If God is all-powerful and is really concerned
about goodness, why is there any evil in the world? If there really is an omnipotent God, why
isn't the world perfect?
A.
Various efforts have been made to address this Problem of Evil
such as (1) claiming that God deliberately limits His own power so that humans
can have free will (but this seems to leave some evils like earthquakes still
unexplained) or (2) pointing out how the various imperfections are needed for
the good of the whole (but Voltaire seems to have sufficiently ridiculed
Leibniz's view that this is the best of all possible worlds) or (3) maintaining
that one must take account of the realm of the afterlife as well as what one
can see in this world (but this seems to be just a vain effort to save one
speculative and unverifiable supposition by resting it on top of another one
just as speculative and unverifiable).
B.
Others addressing this issue have concluded that either (1) God's power
is limited (in which case God seems to need our help) or that (2) God's
goodness is limited (in which case it is questionable whether God is worthy of
being worshipped) or that (3) there isn't any God.
VII. An important step in the evolution of the
idea of God took place when the German Enlightenment philosopher Immanuel
Kant (1724-1804) addressed the issue of whether one can construct a
rational argument to support belief in an omnipotent all-good God.
A.
The Scottish philosopher David Hume (1711-1776) had already marshalled
a rather persuasive collection of arguments against the rationality of believing
in the Christian God.
B.
Unlike Hume, Kant was not interested in undermining traditional religious
belief. Nevertheless he cogently
showed that the traditional arguments advanced to prove that God exists all
fail. This includes the ontological
argument to the effect that the very meaning of the word "God" requires
His existence, the cosmological argument based on the notion that there
must be a supernatural cause to explain the existence of the world, and the teleological
argument that the apparent design in the world requires an intelligent
designer.
C.
Kant claimed that there was no way of proving the existence of an
omnipotent, good God, but that humans had to face the fact that they had to choose
between believing in God and taking morality seriously on the one hand or not
believing in God and having no good reason to be moral on the other. He claimed that it would not be rational
to take morality seriously in a universe which was totally amoral and indifferent
to human values. If there is no God
and the universe itself is totally indifferent to morality and other human
values, if there is no guarantee that good will win out in the end
(which is what belief in an ominipotent God boils down to), it would make no
sense for people to deny themselves something in order to follow moral
principles in those situations when these principles could be ignored at no
cost. In a world without God it might
make sense to appear to be a moral person and get the rewards that come
with that, but it would make no sense whatever to do what is right when it really
hurts to do so (which is what Kant means by moral behavior).
D.
Because of the arguments of Hume and Kant, atheistic existentialist Friedrich
Nietzsche (1844-1900) could announce to the intellectual world that "God
is dead" and that it was time for humans to see themselves as they are,
just one more kind of being on the earth struggling to survive in a universe
totally indifferent to their fate now or in the long run.
VIII. It had become evident that the notion of
"God" involved a combination of both power and goodness and that
there was no reason to believe that the universe was governed by such an unlimited
power that good would prevail in the end.
A.
Given this situation, some religious humanists argued that humans
have to do what is morally right just because it is morally right and not
because there is some other force in the universe which guarantees that good
will prevail in the end or that righteous individuals will in some way be
rewarded for their righteousness.
B. If one uses the term "God" to refer to that which
unites power and goodness and we look at the world to see where there actually
is power working for goodness, it seems that one such place is in the human
beings who work to promote peace and justice and respect for human rights and
long-term improvement of human society and of the world in general.
C. Furthermore, if one looks at reality
objectively, there doesn't seem to be any force working for good anywhere
else. The traditional idea of
"God" must be replaced by a new view of God as the
"spirit" or "force" working for good in some humans on some
occasions.
VIII. A more recent naturalistic understanding
of God has been put forward by Unitarian philosopher and theologian Henry
Nelson Wieman (1884-1975).
A.
Wieman starts with the supposition that "God" must refer to
"The Source of Human Good" (the title of one of his books) as
well as something that can be the object of "Man's Ultimate Commitment"
(the title of another of his books).
B.
Wieman argues that instead of just speculating about this matter we must
empirically investigate to determine what does in fact serve as the source
of human good. His conclusion is
that the source of human good is not something found within particular
humans as the humanists claim but rather a process that takes place in
the world as a whole but especially in human society. In opposition to the humanist view, Weiman notes that individuals
devoted to doing good things can make disastrous mistakes when they are not interacting
with others.
C.
This source of human good which can serve as man's ultimate commitment
is "the process of creative interchange." That process is present when people with
different points of view exchange ideas with open minds and seek creative
solutions to mutual problems. It is the
kind of process which is at work in a truly democratic community. He thinks that it is also at work in
nature in the evolutionary process of chance variation and natural
selection.
D.
Wieman has no compunction about using the word "God" to
describe this process because that word "God" is the word that has
traditionally been used to refer to the source of human good and to the object of
people's ultimate commitment. He
readily admits that people have had traditonal ideas about god being a personal
supernatural being, but he thinks that it is time for people to move on
to a more empirically appropiate view of god (1) which takes account of what
really works for good in the world, (2) which appropriately identifies what
we can commit ourselves to in worship, and (3) which supports our social
practices.
IX. As my title indicates, our views of God are
still evolving and will continue to evolve. The last word has not been said. I hope that this presentation will help the evolution to continue.
Return to First Unitarian Church of Alton - Selected Sermons Page